@cshentrup it would be better to prevent rent collection in the first place. but as a matter of informational and political problems, we seem unable to do that adequately, leading to very grave social harms. we should continue to improve on preventing rent collections, as best we can, but since we are unable to adequately do that, we should seek second-best backstop solutions to address the problem, if we can find backstops that aren't too costly.

in reply to @cshentrup

@czimm_economist no. no. NOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOO!

in reply to @czimm_economist

@cshentrup consider fire insurance. the first best solution is to prevent fires. often we fail. the second best solution is to have sufficient savings to cover eventualities. the third best solution is fire insurance, which creates a lot of deadweight administrative costs relative to the first or second best solution. 1/

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup yet, we find ourselves unable to reliably prevent fires so certainly we don't need to worry about the, um, risk. most of us are not able to save enough to cover that eventuality from savings. so we choose to bear costs of administration—deadweight costs relative to the first or second best solutions—to pay for fire insurance. is that rational, smart, under the circumstances? it depends on the scale of the costs. if premia were much higher than the expected loss, no. if near, yes. 2/

in reply to self

@cshentrup i agree that it would be much better if we could structure the economy so that there were fewer rents and barriers to competition, rather than tax the result of all that at the back end. i very much support antitrust, IP reform, and other policy that would address those problems. but it may in fact be the case, as a matter if real world politics, that we just cannot prevent the rents up, especially given the incentives created by lightly taxed receipt of them. 3/

in reply to self

@cshentrup if the politics of the second best solution — taxing at the back end, both to limit the damage to the distribution and discourage the behavior — are more tractable than the detailed industry-by-industry work challenged at every turn by better funded, better informed lobbyists, then like fire insurance on the back-end, it might be wise to go for the second best. 4/

in reply to self

@cshentrup note, in both cases, the solutions aren't mutually exclusive, and we should always pursue the first best! have fire extinguishers! support antitrust! 5/

in reply to self

@cshentrup but until we succeed at the first best much more fully than we have thus far, we will need to supplement it with the second best.

as long as the costs of the second-best, the backstop, are reasonable! which is why the question of what behavior in fact different taxes would discourage and encourage is the heart of the question. 6/

in reply to self

@cshentrup if i am right that FDR-style taxation discourages very little that is productive and compensation choices that yield a better income distribution, we should do it!

if i am wrong, and in fact FDR-style taxations would lead to an atlas-shrugged style withdrawal by the best and brightest of our community and an economic catastrophe for all, then we should look for different approaches. 7/

in reply to self

@cshentrup there are controversies here, about politics and human behaviors, that math and supply-and-demand diagrams can't solve. even "evidence" can't definitively resolve it, because no experiment or observational study that is plausible is anything near the full policy intervention. 8/

in reply to self

@cshentrup this is true of UBI too, where i think we mostly agree. people argue over incentives to work, etc. most of the evidence that i know of is pretty positive on these grounds, and the non-increase of an effective tax rate is an argument that's labor supportive. but the other side claims the mere reduction of desperation will harm work incentives.

you can't know for sure until you have some history with it. that's just the nature of social affairs! /fin

in reply to self

@cshentrup nice of you to say!

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup taxing rents absolutely affects behavior. that's a good thing! the theory of a land value tax is that you don't have to worry about discouraging land production. but, for example, we do want to discourage the production of lawyers who file patent troll lawsuits. taxing the wages of that kind of activity — rent-seeking — certainly will affect the behavior!

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup that's a large part of why we want to do it! people get paid money for a lot of activities that are not socially useful, but that are a negative social contribution. we want to tax those flows, so that people do less of it. we want to tax the production of bads, which includes activities like exploiting pricing power rather than expanding production to increase profits.

in reply to self

@cshentrup i don't care what fraction of the money derives from rents. i care about the taxes effect on behavior.

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup what's your evidence that whatever social value is incentivized by payments to the very wealthy are larger than the social costs that wealth concentration imposes? you don't show any evidence. you just have priors over what matter more that are, i'd suggest, mistaken.

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup it is you, my friend, who has religion.

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup ok! talk to you later!

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup human affairs aren't math, or decidable by math. math is a tool, which can be wielded well or poorly, but decides nothing. the perfect math of your model will drive you to do the wrong thing when your model is wrong. which it is, very badly, my neoliberal friend.

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup There are more things in heaven and earth, my dear Horatio, than can be drawn as Harberger triangles.

Money and investment are different things. Access to funds flows can sometimes rival rather than support investment. Perfectly rationally, from a shareholders perspective, but not from a social perspective. Those interests are different, and often misaligned.

in reply to @cshentrup

@doriantaylor @mhkohne omg.

in reply to @doriantaylor

@cshentrup i'm not interest in taxing corps. that just encourages bad capstructure, until we also eliminate the tax deductibility of interest. i'm interest in taxing the very wealthy, and am entirely unconcerned that in cohorts among whom money represents score-keeping and zero-sum insurance, changing the baseline of competition by taxing them all equivalent will impair production. concentrated wealth imposes huge costs. taxing the very wealthy is a fiscal positive plus a social gain. win win!

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup (i do have some interest in taxing corp profits, if we can eliminate the deductibility of interest, because doing so encourages reinvesting in whatever creates an asset that firms can expense, including for example adopting a high-investment rather than high-turnover model of labor relations. but a guy who calls himself "neoliberal" is unlikely to be too enthusiastic about that argument.)

in reply to self

@cshentrup (and i'm interested in excess margins taxes, as a means of combatting market power. we want forms to maximize PQ by maximizing Q rather than P. again, i doubt i'm gonna persuade a guy whose moniker is "neoliberal", but this is directly a tax intended to support production rather than rents by reducing the relative value of exploiting pricing power vs expanding production.)

in reply to self

TIL emacs has built-in tetris. my productive life is over.

@cshentrup we can't have perfect information, but i suspect our very different estimates will lead us to very different conclusions. (i gotta run!)

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup neoliberal models tell a really hopeful story about how markets work under the assumption of a close approximation of perfect competition. in the real world, there are lots of things that prevent such an approximation from holding. some of it is physical — Schumpeter famously pointed out that the corner store thrives due to the market power its proximity to some customers confer. 1/

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup "break 'em up" is not always and everywhere the right solution (though we should be doing a whole lot more of it!) but in general we face this challenge: if we want markets to be prosocial, they have to be in fact, not in theory, vigorously competitive, and we'll know that because extraordinary profits will be transient rewards, not permanent franchises. how do arrange that without killing other geese requires detailed attention by industry, i think, rather than broad strokes.

in reply to self

@cshentrup most rents are not government graft. they derive from market power, the ability to prevent competition. Warren Buffet is famously open about how his wealth derives from businesses with moats.

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup under the hypothetical capitalism in neoliberal models, economic profits (ie those above market rates of return on entrepreneur and physical capital inputs) are transient rewards to innovation, for firms that jump ahead until competitors catch up. durable economic profits are rents in the sense they'd not prevail under perfect competition, though we might argue whether some barriers to competition (eg "network effects") are "legitimate".

in reply to self

@cshentrup i am! i think widespread adoption of approval voting is about the lowest-hanging-fruit reform available to us! I'm fond of your nonprofit. I've written about it some, mean to write much more. drafts.interfluidity.com/2023/ drafts.interfluidity.com/2023/ drafts.interfluidity.com/2023/ drafts.interfluidity.com/2023/

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup i think a pretty fundamental point of disagreement between us will likely be our views on the relationship between income and production. i think high levels of income (higher even than yours, this isn't personal) derive almost entirely from rents, and so it is efficient wrt to production to tax it. (rents hinder production by diverting resources to rent-seeking.)

in reply to @cshentrup

@cshentrup i like Kaldor, and i think i've learned that in fact he was very concerned with actual rather than potential redistribution. but the Kaldor-Hicks criterion that has found its way into textbooks demands only that redistribution could be enacted, and licenses economists to declare a policy efficient whether or not politicians actually do. that, it turns out, is incoherent even on narrow economic grounds.

in reply to @cshentrup